14
$\begingroup$

The Krein-Milman theorem asserts that in a locally convex topological vector space, a nonvoid compact convex subset is the closed convex envelope of its extreme points. But I would like to know when it is possible to avoid using Zorn's lemma, in more simple settings (outside of $\mathbb{R}^n$), because for example, in ergodic theory, one can prove quite easily with this theorem that if $X$ is a compact metric space, and $f:X\rightarrow X$ is continuous, and $M_f(X)$ is the set of $f$-invariant probability measures, then the $f$-invariant, ergodic probability measures are the extreme points of $M_f(X)$. The point is that one can prove the existence of $f$-invariant probability measures whithout the axiom of choice.

$\endgroup$
2
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ Do you know this paper by Bell and Fremlin? $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jan 21, 2015 at 10:49
  • $\begingroup$ Should I post it as an answer? Or maybe you should (I have to go now for a while) $\endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jan 21, 2015 at 11:03

1 Answer 1

7
$\begingroup$

The solution is in the comment of Asaf Karagila, which points to the paper "A geometric form of the axiom of choice" by Bell and Fremlin.

In fact, this paper asserts that the assertion : "For every normed vector space $X$ over the reals, there exists at least one extreme point in the unit ball of the continuous dual of $X$" is equivalent to the axiom of choice. So it doesn't matter how nice the space $X$, we can't prove the Krein-Miman for $M(X)=C(X)'$ in ZF. As a corollary, the ultrafilter lemma and the Krein Milman theorem imply (so is equivalent to) the axiom of choice, so the Krein Milman theorem cannot be provable only with the ultrafilter lemma, as the ultrafilter lemma is not equivalent to the axiom of choice. In particular, it shows that we can't prove the Krein Milman theorem without at least a weak form of axiom of choice, and as the ultrafilter is not enough, maybe we really need the axiom of choice in full generality, but the paper doesn't answer this question.

$\endgroup$
5
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ I think it does provide an answer (and the author was invited to post it as such by Asaf), but I agree it ought to be amplified: please say exactly how the paper provides a solution. $\endgroup$
    – Todd Trimble
    Jan 21, 2015 at 11:59
  • 4
    $\begingroup$ There is a quantifier error in the "assertion". The assertion (*) in the paper has an implicit universal quantifier. $\endgroup$ Jan 21, 2015 at 17:18
  • $\begingroup$ @ François G. Dorais. This means that we don't have an answer finally, if the $(*)$ assertion must hold for every normed vector space, this doen't mean that we can't prove the Krein-Milman theorem in simple settings (like my example) without using the axiom of choice. The observation is clear when we look more closely at the proof of $(*) $ implies $AC$. I will edit the answer later. $\endgroup$ Jan 21, 2015 at 22:16
  • 1
    $\begingroup$ I've edited this answer to include (what I perceive to be) the correct quantifier in the quoted text. I'm certainly no set theorist, but I don't think that the axiom of choice - which applies to sets of arbitrarily high cardinality - should be equivalent to a statement about a single set with its one particular cardinality. $\endgroup$
    – Ian Morris
    Feb 11, 2015 at 9:58
  • $\begingroup$ Thank you Mr Morris, I had forgotten about this question, but now the partial answer is correct. $\endgroup$ Feb 12, 2015 at 19:53

Your Answer

By clicking “Post Your Answer”, you agree to our terms of service and acknowledge that you have read and understand our privacy policy and code of conduct.

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged or ask your own question.